Why QBism is completely empty

A good friend of mine, Jacques Pienaar, has recently converted to QBism, as often happens to people that spend too much time around Chris Fuchs. Saddened by these news, I’ve decided to write a blog post explaining why QBism doesn’t contribute anything to understanding Nature. On the contrary, it is a step backwards, as it doesn’t accept the basic premise that there is a world out there and that our job is to understand it. QBism insists that all the puzzles and paradoxes of quantum mechanics don’t actually matter because it’s all subjective anyway.

The first problem with this attitude, of course, is that it’s solipsism. QBists maintain that quantum states are subjective, merely a degree of belief, and therefore everything that is ultimately a quantum state is also subjective: measurement outcomes, Hamiltonians, unitaries, atoms, molecules, trees, capivaras, other people, planets, galaxies, etc. Not yourself, though. Despite being made of atoms, you somehow avoid this subjectiveness, and are unquestionable real. You are also definitely not a quantum state, and cannot be in a superposition. But isn’t that inconsistent with other people being subjective? No, say the QBists. Quantum theory, they maintain, is a single-user theory. You can use it, and it will work for you. Jacques can also use it, and it will work for him. But you both together? Nope, that’s forbidden. And when your predictions conflict with Jacques’? It doesn’t matter, everything is subjective anyway. Hence, solipsism.

Hopefully I don’t need to spend more than a couple of lines explaining why solipsism is such a terrible idea, because I won’t. I’ll merely remark that solipsism can explain any conceivable experience you might have, being therefore no explanation at all. Also that it is not even possible for two different people to agree that solipsism is a great idea, because they will each have their own, incompatible version of solipsism.

Solipsism has such a bad reputation that QBists bristle at this accusation and reply, offended, that of course they are not solipsists, they accept the existence of an objective reality. When pressed on what this objective reality is, then, if not quantum states, they reply that Hilbert space dimension is definitely real. And… that’s it? We just have some Hilbert spaces with some given dimensions, and we’re supposed to model the world with that? Of course not, they say, clearly Hilbert space dimension is not enough. But they can’t say what else is real, and don’t seem terribly interested in finding out. QBism is nearly two decades old, and still they only go on and on about the subjective stuff. I find this attitude incomprehensible. Surely after you identify which parts of your theory are merely subjective, you would discard them and focus on understanding the objective parts, you know, to understand the world out there?

Ok, if they can’t say what is real, can they at least say how their subjective quantum states relate to reality? Are they a probability distribution over the unknown real stuff, as in a $\psi$-epistemic model? Some sort of hidden-variable theory? No, no, no, they say, of course not, they would then be vulnerable to all sorts of no-go theorems. Their quantum states are just beliefs, and how these beliefs relate to reality can never be specified. See, you can never be wrong if you don’t say anything definite!

Let’s turn our attention to the QBist “explanation” for two quantum puzzles. First, the old classic, the nonlocal collapse of the wave function. The explanation, as you might have guessed, is that it doesn’t matter, because the wave function is just subjective anyway. Well, ok, but what happens in reality then? How are the nonlocal correlations produced? Their answer is “Who knows, who cares, and what is this reality thing anyway? And by the way we’re definitely not solipsists!” Over and over again I hear somebody repeating that this QBist “explanation” works as well as the explanation for the nonlocal collapse of classical correlations. It doesn’t. In the classical case the probability distribution that collapses is indeed subjective, arising from ignorance of the actual state of the system. And we can explain how the correlations arise, because the local hidden-variables theory is actually true! Classical relativistic mechanics is indeed local and deterministic. But to apply this explanation to the quantum regime makes no sense: the local hidden-variables theory is not true. And to simply ignore the necessity of being able to produce the correlations in a local way, as the QBists do, is just ridiculous.

The second puzzle is Wigner’s friend, the gedankenexperiment that’s all the rage in the arXiv nowadays. I have explained it in detail before, but the short version is that Wigner’s friend is stuck inside a decoherence-free box, where she makes a measurement on a qubit that’s in the state $\frac{\ket{0}+\ket{1}}{\sqrt2}$. Assuming that the measurement is unitary, this results in the usual world-splitting represented as
\[ \ket{\text{Wigner}}\frac{\ket{\text{friend}_0}\ket{0} + \ket{\text{friend}_1}\ket{1}}{\sqrt2}. \]Wigner will make a measurement of his friend together with the qubit in the Bell basis, expecting to get result $\Phi^+$ with probability 1. If the friend is a Many-Worlder, both of her copies friend$_0$ and friend$_1$ will have no trouble agreeing with this conclusion, but if she is a QBist both of her copies will believe that her measurement caused a collapse, and therefore that Wigner will get result $\Phi^+$ or $\Phi^-$ with probability $1/2$. It takes a bit of mental gymnastics to get to this result, as QBism forbids her from assigning a quantum state to herself and to consider what Wigner will observe. In any case, her expectations are incompatible with Wigner’s, but that’s ok, as everything is subjective anyway and therefore it is not a problem if different agents assign different probabilities to the same event.

That’s what Rüdiger Schack said in a lecture in Vienna several years ago. Apparently this conclusion was too solipsistic even for the QBists, because they recently released a paper with a different take on this: now they refuse to say which probabilities the friend will assign to Wigner’s measurement, saying that it depends on too many things. They emphasize that the friend is not required to agree with Wigner, and that she can anyway learn what the relevant probabilities are if the experiment is repeated many times.

Now that’s just lame. This is a gedankenexperiment, for the love of Zeus, you’re free to specify whatever you think was not precise enough in order to get an answer. Just refusing to give one is the same trick of never being wrong by never saying anything.

That’s why I much prefer Bohmian mechanics and collapse models to QBism. At least they’re trying to do the right thing, and they’re wrong. QBism is not even trying, and is not even wrong.

EDIT: Shortly after posting this I got an angry email from Chris Fuchs. He sent a link to the post to his group, cc’ed to me, with the comment:

An actual scientist would wait until understanding what he was talking about before speaking. But the author of this surely knows his own inadequacies deep inside. My guess is they eat at him.

I think he needs a hug.

This entry was posted in Uncategorised. Bookmark the permalink.

44 Responses to Why QBism is completely empty

  1. Jacques Pienaar says:

    With friends like you Mateus, who needs enemies? It is ironic that although we both went through the Vienna school of Copenhagen, we came out on opposite sides of the force: you a many-worlder and me a QBist. Very well old friend, let us duel.

    But it seems you have come to this battle unarmed — most of your claims about QBism are flatly contradicted by what is written in QBist papers. The only thing you got right was the spelling (with a capital QB, not everyone gets it). You grasp of QBism is so tenuous that rather than reply to your individual points, I’ll have to give a crash course on QBism to set the record straight. Granted, QBism is a weird interpretation by most physicists’ standards, but I hope you’ll see that it’s definitely not solipsism, and it definitely has a unique vision for what quantum theory says about reality.

    EXPERIENCES
    The basic building blocks of reality in QBism are things like `I turned on the laser and saw the red spot’, or `I went to the museum and saw a Van Gogh’. In short they are `experiences’. (Of course, when doing physics experiments we are only interested in a particular subset of experiences, involving sophisticated instruments). The word `experience’ is unfortunate, because when some people hear it they think “oh, experiences happen in the mind”. Their logic goes something like this: “anything that happens must either occur in the world or in my mind. Since the nature of the experience depends on me, it must happen in my mind”. The idea that things must be either in the world or in the mind comes from Descartes, so I’ll call this the Cartesian fallacy. Now repeat after me: `my experience depends on me, but it does not happen inside my mind’. Keep repeating till it makes sense. Here’s a tip: think of any simple, commonplace experience, like sitting down on a chair or taking a bite out of a sandwich. On one hand, that experience definitely depends on you: another person will not experience that chair or sandwich in exactly the same way as you do. On the other hand, you don’t get to control what it is like: it depends on how the world is. If you hate pickles and there’s a pickle in your sandwich, you can’t make it go away just by wishing. So, your experience is unique to you, but it is not in your mind. Ok? Here’s another tip: remember the etymology of `experience’. It comes from `ex-‘, meaning `out’, and `peritus’, meaning `to have gone through’. It is something you get from literally going out and going through something. Or if you’re into philosophy, you could try comparing it to Heidegger’s concept of Dasein. An experience may have `aspects’ of a mental or a worldly character, but in itself an experience belongs to neither category. Once you grasp that, we can discuss reality.

    REALITY
    Take a bunch of experiences. In physics, the experiences are treated kind of like the `initial conditions’ in a physics problem. QBism doesn’t tell you what they are: you have to decide what experiences are relevant to whatever situation you’re trying to model. Quantum theory (according to QBism) just takes the experiences you give it as input, and then gives you a recipe to predict the likelihood of possible future experiences. Remember that experiences make up reality in QBism, so quantum theory takes reality as input and gives you predictions about reality as output. Pretty far from solipsism I’d say.

    AGENTS
    Each experience happens to `someone’, who in QBism is called an `agent’. Just like the experiences themselves, QBism doesn’t tell you what an agent is — you get to decide whether you want to model a given system as an agent or not, and after you make your choice, QBism tells you what to expect based on your choice. There are some minimal guidelines of course: an agent must be able to have experiences. You should consider yourself as the prototypical example of an agent. Beyond that, it’s flexible: maybe for some purposes it might be useful to model a dog, a bee-swarm, a company, or an AI as an agent. Who knows? Try and see if it works. This flexibility is a strength, not a weakness. It allows you to potentially model a wide range of phenomena.

    OBJECTIVITY
    Okay, so QBism is all about reality, but it seems like a kind of `personal’ reality: each experience is only referred to one `agent’. Does this mean two agents cannot have the same experience? If so, wouldn’t that amount to at least a weak kind of solipsism? Not necessarily. Agents can recognize other agents and communicate with them about their experiences. Even if, at a fundamental level, no two agents’ experiences are the same, it is clear that a correspondence of sorts exists between them, and it is this correspondence that gives rise to the `objective character’ of the world. You might not have exactly the same experience of my sandwich as me, but we can be sure it will be similar in a few ways. We might say that experiences have an `inter-subjective’ aspect to them, and our scientific notions of objectivity are founded upon this inter-subjectivity. Exactly how this comes about is still an open question in QBism. That is why although QBism actually says a lot about `reality’, it has so far said very little about `objective’ reality. Hey, it is a hard problem, we are working on it.

    QUANTUM THEORY
    You could think of QBism’s vision of reality as the result of a certain methodological process that is still underway. The process is to take the Ramsey / de Finetti flavour of the subjective Bayesian interpretation of probability, and apply it indiscriminately to every aspect of quantum theory, while at the same time adhering to a version of Einstein’s `program of the real’. (Fun fact: many supposed criticisms of QBism are actually directed at the subjective Bayesian approach to probability, and have little or nothing to do with QBism per se).

    So far, QBism seems to be saying that the world is some kind of complicated mash-up of `experiential reality’ out of which objective things can emerge under the right conditions, but where reality is fundamentally subject-dependent. While it is true that many no-go theorems fail to apply to QBism, this is mainly because QBism’s vision of reality is so radically different that it falls outside the scope of the kinds of ontological models that the no-go theorems are designed to rule out. If we had more people thinking outside the box beyond the standard ontological models framework, someone might actually find a no-go theorem applicable to QBism, which would then tell us something new and interesting.

    LOCALITY
    Admittedly, over time QBists have said contradictory things about locality. Nowadays we don’t claim that quantum theory is `local’, but prefer to say that it is `consistent with causality’ (with caveats), or at least that it is `not non-local’. The truth is, I think, that `locality’ is actually not yet well-defined in QBism, so we simply can’t pose the question yet. I have said the same thing about Rovelli’s relational QM in a paper [https://arxiv.org/abs/1807.06457], but much of what I said there could be applied to QBism as well. In essence, every agent experiences space-time in their own way, so to speak about locality we need to find a way of `stitching together’ the different agents’ space-times into something like an `objective’ space-time manifold, relative to which `locality’ could be defined.

    About Wigner’s friend: I do think you have a point when you accuse QBism of not saying enough about Wigner’s friend. QBism can definitely say more interesting things here, but to do so requires making additional assumptions about the priors of Wigner and the Friend and working out their consequences. Simply put, this work hasn’t been done yet. Although I think Eric Cavalcanti makes a good start of it near the end of his recent paper [https://arxiv.org/abs/2008.05100].

  2. Devin says:

    @Jacques What you write doesn’t really contradict what’s above. The main point I took out of it was that QBism doesn’t say much about objective reality, which you agree with. QBism doesn’t provide any objective model and the idea of an inter-subjective network of experiences is even compatible with many worlds or multi-solipsism.

  3. Mateus Araújo says:

    Thanks for chiming in, Jacques. Well, at least neither of us came out of Vienna as a Copenhagener!

    You haven’t pointed out any contradiction between what I said and the QBists write. I’ll be happy to correct any misrepresentation you can find. I’d just ask a bit more of respect: I do know what I’m talking about, I have read way too many QBist papers. I had in fact a lot of sympathy for QBism until I started reading them more closely.

    As for your main point: I’m well aware that QBists claim that personal experience is real. That’s fine. My experience of biting a sandwich consists of electrical currents in my brain, they are perfectly real and objective. The problem is your refusal to abstract away your subjective experience and get to the objective sandwich. Quantum theory is about sandwiches, not human neurology.

    And it’s rather disingenuous to focus on our appreciation of sandwiches. If our experiences conflict, it’s a rather harmless conflict that can be resolved by understanding that one likes pickles but not the other. It doesn’t bring into question the very existence of the pickle. The conflicts that QBism refuses to solve, or even acknowledge as valid problems, are of a much deeper nature, of Wigner and the friend assigning different quantum states to the same system. How can you not care about solving the conflict? How is it not solipsist to have different people having their own, incompatible realities?

    It’s not enough to merely assert that your theory is not solipsist, you have to actually get out of agents’ heads and describe objective reality. Insofar as QBism talks about subjective experience, it is a solipsist theory. Insofar as it talks about objective reality, well, it’s pretty empty. And after such a long time I cannot take your word for it and have to assume that nothing about objective reality is forthcoming.

    As for locality and Wigner’s friend, I don’t see any contradiction between what I wrote and what you wrote.

  4. Jacques Pienaar says:

    Hi Mateus,

    Let me try to clarify where I think your original post got it wrong. Are you saying that:

    – You agree that reality consists in experiences, which are not in the minds of the agents, and have to do with an extenal world? If so, then it can’t be solipsism by the definition given in the link you posted.

    – You agree that QBism is an ongoing methodological program to identify objective features of experience? And that it proposes at least a couple? If so, then it is not true that QBism doesn’t care about this, makes no effort on this front, or is simply evading it.

    Maybe your complaint is just that QBism is too slow in delivering on its promises, which makes you skeptical that they will ever be able to. That’s a fair criticism, but it’s the only one still standing from your original post as far as I can tell.

    Here’s my defense of QBism’s slowness. Firstly, its core principles were only articulated around 2009. Since then, very few people have worked on it, it’s received little funding, and most QBists’ energy has been wasted in fruitless debates with people who are too lazy to check the definition of `solipsism’. Cut us some slack! Secondly, the project of defining objectivity as an emergent feature of inter-subjective interactions is HARD. Philosophers still argue about it, but I think the finer details are just beginning to be worked out in the philosophy of metrology (mostly by this one guy). QBism has barely had the time to absorb this, let alone incorporate it into our program. Third and finally, what’s the damn hurry? We’re trying get QM right, not convert the masses to our religion by selling them a slick finished product. To quote Schrödinger:

    `In an honest search for knowledge you quite often have to abide by ignorance for an indefinite period. Instead of filling a gap by guesswork, genuine science prefers to put up with it; and this, not so much from conscientious scruples about telling lies, as from the consideration that, however irksome the gap may be, its obliteration by a fake removes the urge to seek after a tenable answer. So efficiently may attention be diverted that the answer is missed even when, by good luck, it comes close at hand. The steadfastness in standing up to a non liquet, nay in appreciating it as a stimulus and a signpost to further quest, is a natural and indispensable disposition in the mind of a scientist.’

  5. Mateus Araújo says:

    That’s not misrepresentation, that’s disagreement.

    I duly noted that QBists claim not to be solipsists; I’m arguing that the actual contents of the interpretation imply otherwise. You profess belief in an external world, but you only ascribe objective reality to your personal experience, that “has to do with an external world”, but which is otherwise unknowable. That sounds like the belief of those Christians that only go to the church on Easter and Christmas. I don’t see a material difference between that and outright denying its existence, saying that all that exists is one’s personal experience. Also, you don’t even pretend to believe in the objective reality of other agents.

    I definitely do not agree that “QBism is an ongoing methodological program to identify objective features of experience”. The problem is not that progress is too slow, the problem is that I don’t see any attempt in this direction. Despite the little funding, there’s a couple of QBist papers every year, and they are all about dismissing aspects of the world as subjective, never about figuring out what the objective reality is. To quote my grandfather: “If you want to find an armadillo you have to search for it”.

    Maybe one day QBism will start doing it, then I’ll change my mind. But the QBism that exists today is just a hidden-variables theory without the hidden variables.

  6. Danylo says:

    After thinking about this objective-epistemic stuff I came to conclusion that the “real” question behind this is how to differentiate “I” (the ego) from the “Environment” (the world around). And I don’t have answer to that – solipsism is obviously wrong, and you are not just your body. You consist of thoughts that are in constant diffusion with other people thoughts. You may claim that a human have a definite (objective) state of mind (and consciousness, whatever this is) in any particular moment. But how we can be sure about this? With all this quantum weirdness…

  7. Mateus Araújo says:

    There’s another point I want to make about no-go theorems. The lack of a precise definition of reality in QBism makes it impossible for it to be a sensible exercise. If I did come up with a definition of reality myself, and provided a no-go theorem based on it, you could simply dismiss that saying that it was not what you meant. You could accuse me of setting up a straw-man just to set it on fire, and it would indeed be precisely what I would be doing. The definition must come from an actual supporter of the theory.

    This is what historically happened with local hidden variables, for example. Einstein gave a definition in the EPR paper that he actually stood behind, and this is what made Bell’s theorem so devastating: it wasn’t attacking a straw-man, but a philosophical position that was actually defended. More recently, the same could be said about $\psi$-epistemic models. Harrigan and Spekkens provided a precise definition, and they in fact deeply cared about them. This did in fact lead to fruitful research and no-go theorems that hurt.

  8. Jacques Pienaar says:

    “Get out of agents’ heads?” So you think that `experience’ happens inside agents’ heads: you’re stuck in a Cartesian worldview. For you, subjective means `of the mind’, and objective means `of the mind-independent world’. To be fair, this is what most physicists would understand by those words, having been brought up in the Cartesian way of thinking. And on these terms, I think it would be fair to call QBism solipsist. But that would me missing the point, because QBism explicitly says that is not how we should think about experience, objectivity, and subjectivity.

    So how do we think about it? Let’s take the example of a chair. Suppose I experience bumping into the chair and hurt myself. A QBist would say that’s mostly subjective, because it only happened to me. But it is also a little bit objective because it involves an object, namely the chair, which is experienced by me as something external to my own consciousness. Now suppose you also bump into it, and 1000 other people bump into it, and we discuss our experiences and establish that we’re all talking about the same chair. Now the chair is a lot more objective and a lot less subjective. So for QBists, subjectivity and objectivity come by degrees, they are not all-or-nothing propositions. And the agents’ experiences just exist, they are not `inside a mind’ or `inside a world’. If anything, mind and world are to be found inside the experience!

    I get that this might sound like nonsense to you, if you’ve only ever known the Cartesian way of thinking. I want to emphasize that QBists didn’t invent this. The idea that experience is more fundamental than the mind-world split has a mature philosophical tradition behind it. For me, the main reference for this way of thinking is the philosophical school of `Phenomenology’, which goes back to Husserl from the 1930s onwards. The book Phenomenology: the Basics by Dan Zahavi is very readable and I think is essential for everyone interested in QBism. There’s also a movement in cognitive science called enactivism, whose approach to consciousness is very QBism compatible.

    This is also relevant to your comment about no-go theorems and ontological models. The nice thing about Cartesian thinking is that you can cleanly separate the `elements of reality’ from `measurements’. Then you just represent them by mathematical symbols and come up with a function that combines them to give you something obersvable, and voilà, you have an ontological model! In our case the elements of reality refer to an external world but on the other hand are inextricable from the measurements themselves. Just take a look at Chapter 2 of Zahavi’s book, which deals with the relationship between mind and world, and tell me what the hell would a mathematical model of that look like? It beats me! Lorenzo Catani tells me he has an idea that might work for QBism, using `point-free topological spaces’. It might work, but it sure won’t fit into the world of Harrigan and Spekkens.

    Sure, I can see how to a skeptic on the outside it might seem like we secretly want to remain vague so that we can never get caught out. But I’m telling you, as an insider, that we’d love to have an ontology that can be attacked and examined by the community. We’ve been having group meetings about QBist ontology since June. It’s just bloody hard to invent one, because this is still quite unfamiliar territory. I’d be willing to bet with you that QBism will endorse at least one proposed ontology by the end of 2022. Is it cheating if I end up proposing it myself?

    PS. Where do you get that QBists “don’t even pretend to believe in the objective reality of other agents”? I’m genuinely confused how you got that idea. I can tell you with absolute certainty that every QBist believes in the reality of multiple agents.

  9. Mateus Araújo says:

    Yeah, I’m stuck in a Cartesian worldview. Also known as using the words objective and subjective in the way they’re usually understood. You’re trying to evade the accusation of solipsism by changing the very meaning of objective. That’s intellectual dishonesty.

    I’m skeptical that you can get any coherent ontology using these degrees of objectivity and making experience the fundamental building block of reality. Or perhaps you will, simply by redefing what an ontology is.

    In any case, I’m glad to hear that you are actually working on an ontology. When it shows up on the arXiv I’ll change my mind about QBism. Provided, of course, that it is an actual ontology according to my definition. Not that I’m demanding it to fit into the Harrigan&Spekkens framework. That’s just one way to formalise it, and one that already has plenty of no-go theorems against it.

    About the reality of other agents: the interpretation is quite explicit that you also assign a quantum state to other agents, and they are as subjective as anything else. Perhaps you mean that you believe in their reality in a informal, pre-theoretic kind of way. I’m talking about how they are actually formalised in the interpretation.

  10. Jacques Pienaar says:

    Well, I don’t know what you think QBism gains from its supposed ‘intellectual dishonesty’… all it seems to do is make people think we’re solipsists! But I concede that it’s our burden to be clear about what we mean by ‘subjective’ and ‘objective’, and it is hard to find a complete and unambiguous discussion of this point in the literature. That’s because we’re still in the early days of articulating this, and it is tricky business.

    On a more technical point: in QBism we usually assume (implicitly) that all agents agree that there is a system, and what its dimension is, even if they disagree about its state. Of course, this assumption can always be questioned within QBism, since at bottom, even the notion of a system of some dimension has to be founded on the experiences of individual agents. Roughly speaking there is a hierarchy of objectivity, depending on how stable a given belief has proven to be against the arrival of new facts.

    For example, in a typical lab situation, it is quite likely that something could happen that would cause you to revise the state you assigned to an electron, but comparatively unlikely that something would happen to cause you to believe it is a photon instead of an electron. So in that context we’re entitled to have the prior belief that ‘the system is an electron’ and call it objective. Similarly, when you assign a state to another agent, you might plausibly revise the state you assign to them based on your interactions with them, but nothing they do is likely to make you suddenly realize that they are, in fact, a wooden table. So in this context we can say ‘the fact of an agent’ is about as objective as ‘the fact of a table’ or ‘the fact of an electron’, while at the same time insisting that the ‘state’ of these objects can be largely subjective.

  11. Mateus Araújo says:

    So not even the Hilbert space dimension is completely objective in QBism? This is getting rather frustrating.

    I suppose the point is that you can’t really make a superposition of a photon and an electron, so you can’t formulate the usual puzzles of quantum mechanics by using the photoness versus electroness property. Therefore, you don’t insist that this property must be subjective, as you don’t seem to get into trouble otherwise.

    Except, though, you can. Pair production transforms a photon into an electron-positron pair. As it’s fundamentally random, you do get a superposition of the transformation having occurred or not. Or, more prosaically, neutron decay. It will be in a superposition of being a neutron and a proton-electron pair. I suppose then you’d shift your not-quite-subjective system to being the appropriate bosonic or fermionic fields, and the subjective state to being the number of excitations in each field. The Hilbert space dimension should then shift from being the dimension of whatever degree of freedom you were interested in, to being the usual infinite dimension of QFT.

  12. Yash Sharma says:

    Hello,
    About the part where Jacques Pienaar described the reality aspect of QBism –
    ‘Quantum theory (according to QBism) just takes the experiences you give it as input, and then gives you a recipe to predict the likelihood of possible future experiences.’

    The agent instantiates one experience, but what happened to all the other experiences that were also predicted with a certain probability?

    Many worlds says that all those remaining experiences happen as well, and collapse theories say through some contrived mechanism that only one happens.

    How does QBism do away with all the other experiences?
    (I know exceptionally little about physics, so if my questions are completely off the mark please correct.)

  13. Mateus Araújo says:

    Yash Sharma,

    Your question is right on spot. There isn’t a satisfactory answer, though, precisely because of what I’ve been complaining about all this time: QBism refuses to say anything about objective reality.

    Since QBists insist that the collapse is only subjective, and the probabilities are only subjective, I think what it would make sense is to say that the experience that was instantiated was pre-determined by a hidden variable, and the probabilities are just ignorance of which value the hidden variable actually took. Just how it is in Bohmian mechanics.

    You can be sure, though, that QBists will emphatically say that this is not the case, that theirs is not a hidden-variables theory. But they won’t say what is going on, they won’t go for real collapse, Many-Worlds, or hidden variables.

  14. Jacques Pienaar says:

    Hi Yash Sharma,

    When you ask ‘what happens’ to the unrealized possibilities, it sounds like you are presuming that, in some sense, these possibilities ‘exist’ even before they are measured. But a QBist would say ‘possibile events’ do not exist, so it does not make sense to ask ‘what happens to them’ when some event occurs. When something happens, it is real, but we cannot say that it was real before it happened.

    Think of a coin. Before you flip it, you say that there are two possibilities: either it will be heads, or tails. If you believe in an objective interpretation of probability (like Mateus does), then this is a statement about the physical properties of the coin itself: `the possibility of heads’ and `the possibility of tails’ correspond to something that really exists in the coin.

    It might be that you think there is a variable that determines what the outcome will be, which is unknown to you, but which is the only possibility and it exists even before you flip the coin. This would be similar to the hidden variables interpretation. Or it might be that you think the coin has an intrinsic `tendency’ to land either heads to tails, and this tendency is an objective physical property of the coin. When you flip it and get, say, heads, then this property physically changes into `heads’, and the possibility of tails is `destroyed’ in the process. This is similar to an `objective collapse’ interpretation. Finally, you might think that `tails’ is not destroyed, but simply happens in a parallel part of the multiverse, to an exact copy of you. This would be similar to the ‘many worlds’ interpretation. All of these options treat the ‘possibilities’ as describing something real about the coin.

    QBism rejects all of those interpretations. QBism says that before we flip the coin, the possibilities of heads and tails simply do not exist. A ‘possibility’ just means something we think might happen, but it does not correspond to anything actual in the world. The possibility of heads or tails before you flip the coin does not say anything about the coin itself: it only says something about what you think might happen in the future, and nothing more.

    When you flip the coin, something just spontaneously happens, and whatever happens is real in the moment that it happens. However, it did not come from something that existed before. It was created in the moment that the coin was observed.

    We like to think of it as similar to the Big Bang. In some cosmological models, the Big Bang was not caused by anything that existed previously. For QBism, every time you flip a coin and get a result, you have made a `little bang’ (Chris Fuchs calls it a QBoom). This little bang brings something new into reality that never existed before. By flipping the coin and observing the outcome, you have participated in creating a tiny piece of the universe.

    Notice that I say ‘participated’. That is because although you played a part in it, you do not get to say what actually happens. That is up to the world. As Anton Zeilinger once said, ‘There are two fundamental freedoms: our freedom to define which measurement apparatus to use and thus to determine which quality can become reality; and Nature’s freedom to give the answer she likes’.

  15. Mateus Araújo says:

    That’s just avoiding the question. You can’t escape Maudlin’s trilemma: to solve the measurement problem you have to either

    1. give up the assumption that the quantum state encodes everything about the relevant physics (e.g. by postulating hidden variables).
    2. give up the assumption that the quantum state evolves linearly (e.g. by having a physical collapse).
    3. give up the assumption that measurements have a single outcome (i.e. going Many-Worlds).
  16. Yash Sharma says:

    Hello Jacques Pienaar,
    From your explanation i am able to understand a little better how QBism views ‘multiple possibilities’ and that it considers them as not being real. In case of the coin flip example, it is clear.

    But how does this view explain situations where interference is actively exploited, such as in the case of Shor’s algorithm. The result and the measurement of the output of the algorithm can be understood in terms of an agent and its experience. But how do we explain with QBism, the underlying reality that makes it possible for a quantum computer to perform those computations?

  17. Jacques Pienaar says:

    @Mateus: Suppose you keep saying to me `in chess you only have two options: either you choose black or white. Now choose.’ And suppose I keep saying to you, `but we are playing Scrabble’. Am I avoiding your question, or are you avoiding my answer?

    Maudlin assumes that the quantum state is (directly or indirectly) a representation of a system’s physical properties. He takes this for granted and never acknowledges that it is an assumption. We physicists are all raised on this dogma: starting from the measured properties of a system, we are supposed to infer its present ‘state’. We then we apply the laws of physics to we predict the future state, and thereby predict its future measurable properties. Okay, so physics begins and ends with measured properties, and those at least correspond to reality. The ‘states following laws’ simply tells us how to get from presently measured reality to future measurable reality. But does that mean the states themselves represent anything real? There are ways to make the exact same predictions without using the notion of ‘states following laws’ at all.

    To put it bluntly, in QBism, the state is not a representation of a system’s real properties — not directly or indirectly, not completely or partially. We don’t need a ‘state’ to be able to talk about reality. QBism is not susceptible Maudlin’s trilemma because it rejects the premises on which it is founded.

  18. Mateus Araújo says:

    This option falls squarely within Maudlin’s framework. If a quantum state is not a representation of a system’s real properties – either directly, indirectly, completely, or partially – it is in particular not a complete representation of the relevant physics. You’re choosing alternative 1, then.

    The only implicit assumption he makes is that there are real properties. If you deny that, sure, you escape his trilemma. But then you’re also a solipsist.

  19. gentzen says:

    Maybe Maudlin himself formulated his trilemma more carefully, but I have the feeling that the given formulation is either not applicable to some analyses via “carricature decoherence setups”, or else makes a ton of unstated assumptions. Such a carricature uses
    three nested systems:

    Many attempts to interpret quantum mechanics do so by looking at three nested systems. The largest system is essentially the universe or the environment. The smallest system is the one being observed and following the laws of the theory, and the middle system contains the measurement device or the observer.

    So there are at least three different states which must be distinguished:
    (1) The “known” quantum state of the smallest system which is observed. This one does have a collapse, so it does not (always) evolve linearly.
    (2) The “unknown” quantum state of the middle system containing the smallest system and the measurement device (but probably not the observer), for which at least the “relevant” laws how the “unknown” quantum state evolves should still be postulated. This one has an evolution that should be approximately linear (no longer a collapse, just a weak coupling to an environment).
    (3) Both the state and the evolution of the enviroment are unknown. Maybe gravity or something else induces some non-linear evolution, maybe not. However, they are mostly “irrelevant” for predictions concerning the smallest system.

    The measurement happens on the measurement device in the middle system. Somehow this measurement device has some equivalence classes of macroscopic states which are distinguishable with near certainty. It also has states that don’t fall into one of those equivalence classes, but as long as it is in such an unclear state (like a superposition of a dead and an alive cat), it does not yet make sense to talk of a measurement.

    This description has not given up (3) “the assumption that measurements have a single outcome”, because it only talks about measurement if there actually was a single macroscopic measurement result with near certainty.
    It neither affirmed nor explicitly denied (2) “that the quantum state evolves linearly”. OK, it denied it for the quantum state of the smallest system, retreated to “approximately linear” for the middle system, and claimed to stay agnostic for the environment. So it basically gave up the assumption that the “relevant quantum states evolve exactly linearly”.
    It claimed that the quantum state of the middle system (1) “encodes everything about the relevant physics”, where “relevant” has to be understood in an appropriate way.

    Now you might claim that this analysis proves that Maudlin’s trilemma applies to this carricature, because point (2) did apply. But this misses the actual weak points of the carricature: (a) The “equivalence classes of macroscopic states which are distinguishable with near certainty” are subjective. The equivalence classes are not given objectively by themselves. (b) No indication is given why a measurement should actually occur, i.e. why the measurement device should evolve into one of the “macroscopic states which are distinguishable with near certainty”.

  20. Mateus Araújo says:

    Maudlin did formulate his trilemma very carefully. You could just read his paper, I linked it above.

    I don’t see what is the point you’re trying to make. If you do go for option 2 you can solve the measurement problem, this is well known. Now if whatever you propose actually does it or suffers some other problem is besides the point.

  21. gentzen says:

    My point was that it was unclear to me how “carricature decoherence setups” based on three nested systems were supposed to be matched to Maudlin’s trilemma. There are three states (two of them definitely quantum states) in the carricature, hence it was unclear to me which of those three states Maudlin intended to talk about. And it was also unclear to me what would count as measurement for him. Note that in the carricature, a measurement has only happened after the measurement device evolved into one of the equivalence classes of macroscopic states which are distinguishable with near certainty.

    After reading the article, I learned that what counts as measurement for Maudlin is the interaction itself between the smallest system (which is observed) and the measurement device. (This part I guessed wrong in my previous comment.) I also learned that the quantum state Maudlin intends to talk about is the quantum state of the middle system. (This part I guessed right in my previous comment.)

    I agree that the article itself is clear and very carefully formulated. The article also contains two explicit versions of the trilemma, but only the third point about measurements is formulated significantly more careful than your formulation. (The main difference between the two explicit versions is in this third point, which is probably the reason why Maudlin tried to formulate it very carefully.) Here are Maudlin’s two explicit versions of his trilemma:

    The following three claims are mutually inconsistent.
    The wave-function of a system is complete, i.e. the wave-function specifies (directly or indirectly) all of the physical properties of a system.
    The wave-function always evolves in accord with a linear dynamical equation (e.g. the Schrödinger equation).
    Measurements of, e.g., the spin of an electron always (or at least usually) have determinate outcomes, i.e., at the end of the measurement the measuring device is either in a state which indicates spin up (and not down) or spin down (and not up).

    Formally, the following three claims are mutually inconsistent:
    The wave-function of a system is complete, i.e. the wave-function specifies (directly or indirectly) all of the physical properties of a system.
    The wave-function always evolves in accord with a deterministic dynamical equation (e.g. the Schrödinger equation).
    Measurement situations which are described by identical initial wave-functions sometimes have different outcomes, and the probability of each possible outcome is given (at least approximately) by Born’s rule.

    Independent of whether those two explicit versions would be enough to identify the measurement part as the weak point of the carricature, reading the article itself makes it clear that this would be Maudlin’s conclusion (which would be spot on). His analysis and proofs however don’t apply directly to the carricature. Still they do provide a good starting point for an analysis which does apply to the carricature.

  22. Jacques Pienaar says:

    @Yash Sharma:

    Your question about quantum computing hits close to home for me. In the end, the ultimate test of whether an interpretation is accepted by the physics community is not whether it is right or wrong in some abstract philosophical way, but whether it can naturally explain the things we find in our laboratories. I don’t think QBism is likely to be proven wrong, absurd, or inconsistent on purely logical grounds — it is too sophisticated for that. The real danger to QBism is actually of an empirical nature (a fact that our critics seem unable to grasp): if quantum theory breaks down at some scale, then QBism will be unable to explain that, and would be thrown out. And even if quantum theory holds at all scales, QBism might still fail, if it cannot provide intuitive explanations for important quantum phenomena. For without that, it would never attract the attention of most of the physics community and will eventually be forgotten.

    The question of why quantum computers give an advantage over classical computers is exactly the kind of thing we would hope be answerable by appealing to the ontology of quantum theory. On this particular issue, many-worlds seems to have the upper hand so far: folklore has it that David Deutsch was inspired to invent quantum computing because the parallel universes suggested to him an analogy with parallel processing in computation. There are subtleties with the analogy (we can’t simply access those parallel worlds without restrictions), but many people do see this as a point in favour of many-worlds. Can QBism answer to that?

    I don’t know yet, but think QBism can definitely give us a different perspective on computation in general. We are used to thinking of computation as something akin to a property of a physical system. But QBists would say, along with Turing, that computation is primarily a human activity. Turing’s famous machine was not supposed to be an abstraction of a physical system — it was supposed to be an abstraction of a particular kind of human activity. It was Deutsch who placed the emphasis on physical systems. Of course, he would not have made a distinction between ‘human activity’ and ‘a physical system obeying natural laws’ — that distinction would only make sense to a QBist. But that is precisely my point: for a QBist, the way that we think about computation would have to be revised to bring it more in line with Turing’s original conception. Then the way in which QBism would update the idea of a ‘Turing machine’ in light of quantum theory might take us down a different route than the one followed by Deutsch. I don’t know if that route would explain the quantum speedup, but I definitely think it would be interesting to pursue.

  23. ppnl says:

    I wonder if you smart guys could answer a few questions That I think are relevant.

    1)What is the difference between an “agent” and a preferred basis?

    2)How does QBism differ from simple decoherence?

    I think it is inevitable that we will have to accept a subjective component to quantum mechanics. But by “subjective” I do not mean the conscious experience of an observer. I simply mean the point of view of some preferred basis.

    So the whole thing reduces to the preferred basis problem. Where does it come from? I don’t think quantum mechanics can answer that. But I don’t think it needs to. Some things just are. There may be a deeper answer beyond QM but if so I suspect it will be even less kind to a mind demanding classical answers.

  24. Mateus Araújo says:

    Both of your questions are like asking what is the difference between a crow and a poem. They just don’t have anything to do with eachother. Maybe I can say something useful about the second question, though; decoherence is not an interpretation, is just the physical mechanism by which interference between two terms of a superposition are suppressed by the relentless entangling with the environment. It’s happening whether you believe it or not.

    The preferred basis problem was open decades ago. It has been solved precisely by the advent of decoherence theory. The preferred basis is the basis of the pointer states, the ones that are stable under decoherence. It goes by the catchy name of quantum Darwinism.

  25. ppnl says:

    Then I have no idea what an “agent” or “belief” is. I presume a person can be an agent. But how about an artificially intelligent robot? A measuring device? A rock? All of these can cause decoherence but what test could you do to determine if something is an agent or if it just causes decoherence? The whole problem seems as empty as Searle’s Chinese room. An agent becomes simply something that has Searle’s special substance or process that allows intentional states.

    I confess I just don’t get quantum Darwinism. First I don’t see anything Darwinistic about it. Second, I don’t see what it adds that isn’t immediately obvious given decoherence.

    Consider two particles whose spin states are entangled. The strange apparent non-local effects are just a consequence of conservation of spin. More generally you have conservation of information. Consider a larger system of particles like a cat in a box with a vial of cyanide. The state of the cat is entangled with the state of the cyanide such that you can never observe a dead cat and an unbroken vial. The reality we see is just a vast network of entangled states. That vast network contains a vast amount of information that must be conserved. That is the origin of the apparent classical universe.

    And I don’t agree that decoherence solves the preferred basis problem. There are a vast number of possible futures that are consistent with current information. You still need the Born rule to select which becomes real. And that future seemingly classical universe can ask why them rather than some other consistent possibility. Why did they become the new basis state?

    I just don’t think the preferred basis problem is a problem that QM needs to answer and it probably isn’t a problem that needs an answer at all.

  26. Mateus Araújo says:

    You seem to be confusing the preferred basis problem with the measurement problem. Take a look here. It is an explicitly Many-Worlds problem, so it doesn’t make sense to ask which of the possible futures is real. All of them are.

    As for agents, Jacques Pienaar wrote about the QBist definition of them (or lack thereof) in a comment above. I can’t do better than him, as I don’t think the concept makes much sense, or has any place in a fundamental theory.

  27. ppnl says:

    I don’t think I am confusing the preferred basis problem with the measurement problem. In fact I am banned from Lubos Motl’s site because I did not confuse the two. Well, mostly it was because I suggested that he was an anti-quantum zealot. You need to know Lubos to see how funny that is. I was disappointed to later find that I was not the first to play that joke.

    The measurement problem simply asks what a measurement is. And when does wave collapse happen. Some people think, apparently including Lubos, that consciousness causes collapse. Decoherence settles this nicely.

    The preferred basis problem is different. Any measurement must be made with respect to a basis. Where does that bases come from?

    Consider a cat. It is a macroscopic object intimately connected to the environment. It would seem to be a fine preferred basis. But now lets put the cat in a box that isolates it from the external world. Along with it we put in a certain deadly apparatus. Can it still be considered a preferred basis? Contrary to the apparent claims of quantum Darwinism it’s classical state is not stable. It is a superposition of a vast number of states that can be sorted and classified as alive or dead states. In principle you could even prepare two cats in two boxes such they are entangled. Then we can make careful measurements of the cats and get a violation of Bell’s inequality. In that sense there is no difference between a cat and a photon with respect to quantum mechanics.

    So why does the cat split into a many superposed states while we in the external world remain a stable preferred basis? Well from the cat’s perspective we don’t. From the cat’s perspective it is we who have blurred into a superposition of a vast number of possibilities.

    And this is the answer to the preferred basis problem at least in the sense that it can have an answer. The preferred basis is irreducibly subjective. But I don’t mean subjective in the sense of a conscious observer. A rock can count as an observer in as much as it starts in a particular state and you do measurements with respect to the rock. If you are in thermodynamic contact with the rock then you will agree with it. If not then the rock is in a superposition of states. It isn’t about Darwinism or stable pointer states. It is just the flow of information and conservation laws.

    You can see this explicitly in a quantum computer. Say you have a large quantum computer that allows an atom level simulation of the cat in the box. This would allow you to have a software cat that is in actual superposition. A quantum computer has to use reversible logic gates. Why? Irreversible logic gates necessarily emit heat. That heat puts them in thermodynamic contact with the external world. Information is no longer conserved in the quantum calculation. The cat will be in a particular state.

    Jacques Pienaar above seems to be trying to carve out a role for consciousness with his “agent” and “believe” language. That is what prompted my question about agents and preferred basis. My question to him pretty much mirrored my questions to Lubos. Until he can answer it or at least make it clear what he is trying to do he has to join Lubos in the ranks of the anti-quantum zealots.

  28. Mateus Araújo says:

    I have a feeling that Luboš might have banned you because you have no idea what you’re talking about and insists on your ignorance instead of familiarizing yourself with the literature.

    No, that’s not the measurement problem, and decoherence does not solve it. Take a look at Maudlin’s paper that I mentioned above for a good definition of it.

    As for the pointer states, you’re missing the point that they must be stable under decoherence, not stable period. The states $\ket{\text{dead}}$ and $\ket{\text{alive}}$ are stable under decoherence, so they are pointer states. If you put the cat in a box you suppress decoherence, and the superposition state $\ket{\text{dead}} + \ket{\text{alive}}$ becomes stable, but this does not make it a pointer state, because it is still not stable under decoherence.

  29. ppnl says:

    Yeah, I’m not going to spend $40 on this. I do have problems with the abstract and I suspect most of the physics community does as well. On googling him I… well… no. He is a philosopher. In his own words he is attempting to convince the whole physics community that it is deluded. Calling Lubos an anti-quantum zealot was mostly a joke but Maudlin is the real deal.

    Further googling shows Lubos agrees with me rather sharply as is his style. I will give a link but if you are not prepared to see the humor in Lubos I suggest you put on your asbestos underwear.

    [removed link]

    Back to decoherence basics. Say you have a beam of electrons that you want to do a double slit experiment with. But lets say your electron beam is passing through a background of photons. The photons can interact with the electrons slightly changing their path length to the detector. This causes variations in the phase of the electrons. This causes fuzziness in your interference pattern. Enough photons and you can’t see any interference effect at all. Decoherence. In thermodynamics terms the electrons are in thermodynamic contact with the environment. In information theory terms the electrons are exchanging information with their environment. In quantum terms the electrons are not evolving unitarily.

    Now lets do the double slit experiment without the photons but with measuring devices on the slits. Because of the measurement the wave function collapses and you see no interference pattern. How does this work? Just like the photons the measuring device interact with the electrons causing the electrons to change phase in random ways. This causes the interference pattern to fuzz out and disappear. Decoherence. In thermodynamics terms the electrons are in thermodynamic contact with the environment. In information theory terms the electrons are exchanging information with their environment. In quantum terms the electrons are not evolving unitarily.

    Decoherence is wave collapse. A measurement is just a special case of decoherence where the information is preserved in a state we can easily read.

    Now the cat in the box. The whole point of the box is that it prevents thermodynamic contact or information transfer across the boundary. As a practical matter the box is impossible.

    Quantum computers make the connection with information theory explicit. Say you want to multiply three and four with a quantum computer. The problem is that such a calculation loses information. You cannot tell from the output whether you have multiplied three and four or two and six. This is not a unitary operation. Thermodynamics demand that your computer radiate heat.

    To do it on a quantum computer you must use reversible logic gates that preserve information about the inputs. Then in principle you can put the gates in a box so that they are in a superposition of doing many different operations allowing you to factor large numbers.

    Its all about the flow of information. You don’t need QBism as far as I can tell with limited understanding. You don’t need any kind of Darwinism. You don’t even need many worlds but that at least is a good way to visualize things.

  30. Mateus Araújo says:

    This is the last comment from you that I’m going to approve. I have zero tolerance for wilful ignorance. Gratuitous insults against philosophy in general and against Maudlin in particular are not welcome either. I also removed your link to Luboš’ blog, I’m not letting you advertise that garbage here.

  31. Ronald Green says:

    I am in considerable sympathy with QBism, since it parallels my own philosophical work.

    What really surprises me in the above discussion is the emphasis on ‘objective reality’, especially on Mateus’s constant harping on it, taking for granted that such an animal ‘exists’ while at the same time dismissing the role of the observer.

    The fact that scientists chase ‘objective reality’ as a goal, when the very concept should have been dismissed as soon as QM was discovered, is amazing. How could probabilities be objective, never mind objectively real? How could a particle, once found, have an objective reality (existence)? What would that even mean for a ‘point’ that is a mathematical expression representing a ‘thing’ that has physical expression?

    To accept the concept of ‘objective reality’ would mean dismissing subjectivity as unreal, merely the result of consensus. and that somewhere ‘out there’ is the untestable and unfalsifiable Kantian ‘thing in itself’.

    Of course people agree that they are seeing the same things. Surely, though, it is
    a dubious proposition to dismiss the fact that no two people physically do so, due to the non-simultaneousness of light hitting each person according to location, not to mention the constantly changing aspect of time.

    It is understandable that scientists believe in an objective reality. Yet to do so despite their own findings and without questioning what those findings point to, is self-deception on the circular road to untestable theories of of what is ‘true’.

    This is where QBism comes in. As an interpretation of QM, it is a welcome theory that puts the observer where he/she should be. In fact, how could any theory be viable that does not take into consideration an observer (in QBism’s term, ‘the agent’) who, after all, puts forward that theory?

  32. Mateus Araújo says:

    Did you mean seriously the question in your last paragraph? Any theory other than quantum mechanics excludes the observer – general relativity, Newtonian mechanics, electromagnetism – do you consider all of them non-viable? And even within quantum mechanics, there are plenty of observer-less interpretations: many-worlds, Bohmian mechanics, objective collapse.

    In any case, I do take for granted that an objective reality exists, and that my job as a scientist is to explain it. I mean, what else should I study? The illusions produced by Descartes’ demon?

    As for your specific questions: objective probability is indeed a tricky problem, but I have managed to solve it. As for a particle, sure they exist, what is the problem with that? Are you worried about pointlike particles, like the electron? As far as we know they don’t have any spatial extent. It might sound weird, but that’s just life.

    As for people seeing the same thing: they get some photons in their eyes. Which are different photons, of course, even emitted at different times, but they can extrapolate that these photons were reflected (or emitted) by the same thing. Otherwise it would be a big mystery why everybody reacts as if there is a turd on the sidewalk if in reality there’s no turd there.

  33. Ronald Green says:

    Of course I was serious. I am not in the habit of making statements that don’t make sense, such as, for example, that observers make statements without observers, including themselves. You’re not saying, are you, that theories are posited by … what, exactly? By no one? (I believe Newton was a person, as was Einstein. I seriously don’t understand your position.)

    Strange that your job as a scientist is to explain something that you ‘take for granted’ exists. No, your job is to come up with the best explanation for natural phenomena, while knowing that a better explanation will come along.

    It’s good you believe that a particle exists, without even knowing what ‘exists’ means in QM. I don’t think scientists shrug their shoulders when they don’t understand something and say “that’s life.”

    Your last paragraph was a red herring. Of course we extrapolate that we see the same red, for example? Do you really know that you see exactly the same red as someone else does?

  34. Mateus Araújo says:

    Newtonian mechanics was developed by Newton. It does not concern observers. I don’t think either of these statements is controversial or even interesting, so what the hell are you talking about?

    What are these “natural phenomena” that you speak of? Presumably not part of some objective reality, that you reject, but then of what? My head? Your head? Descartes’ demon?

    You are mixing up two different things here: the wavelength of the photon, that’s perfectly objective, and the sensation it induces in your brain, that is subjective. We can perfectly well agree that a source is emitting photons with wavelength 700 nm, that we both call red. Now whatever difference about how we perceive it is due to how our brains process visual signals, and does not call into question the objective existence of a 700 nm photon.

  35. Ronald Green says:

    Newton was not an observer? You seem to think that science works without anyone doing it or knowing about it.

    Regarding natural phenomena, for whom are they natural? For whom are they phenomena? What is objective reality? Objective to everyone?

    I know what wavelengths are. I asked you if everyone sees red in the same way. You certainly can’t know that. As for the wavelength itself, you are, I suppose, aware that the exact length is according to the measurement device being used. The result will never be exact, and hence cannot be said to be objectively real.

  36. Mateus Araújo says:

    You are being disingenuous about the distinction between the person who developed the theory, the person that uses the theory, and how the theory itself describes the world. I don’t believe for a second that you actually have any difficulty with these concepts. Frankly, there’s no point in continuing a discussion at this level.

  37. Ronald Green says:

    I have only one concept: there need to be observers. You seem to find that difficult, and I don’t know why. A theory needs to be BY someone, even if only for himself. No people, no theories.

  38. Devin Bayer says:

    Hello Mateus, I am a many-worlder but I have been thinking for a while that QBism might have a place from an MWI perspective, at least given the assumption that self-locating uncertainty (SLU) is a real phenomenon. (I consider the reality of SLU an open question).

    When one is considering a single system they can use MWI to describe its evolution, including all the observers in it. This mostly tells them what the observers will experience, but if SLU is real then the subjective experience of an observer will not be limited to that single system; they will need to consider all the copies of the observer in other similar systems; to weigh those copies based on how much their subjective descriptions of psi overlap.

    Because of this, the objective system one must consider to fully describe one observer’s subjective experience is everywhere in the complete wavefunction of the universe where a similar version of him exists. To describe all observers requires the complete wavefunction.

    I think this is what QBism is getting at. The complete wavefunction is probably undescribable since there is always a larger Hilbert space; if there is a limit at all it likely contains no information. So to describe the subjective experience of an observer means one should only consider their subjective description of psi.

    I am curious what you think of this take on QBism.

  39. Mateus Araújo says:

    What do you mean by SLU? If you are talking about the idea that after splitting an observer will be uncertain about in which branch of the universe they are, and that this self-locating uncertainty can be measured by the mod-square amplitudes, then I think it is clearly real; the only disagreement I’m aware about is whether this is just one kind of uncertainty that arises in Many-Worlds (my opinion), or it is the source of all uncertainty, as defended by Sebens, Carroll, and Vaidman.

    You seem to have something else in mind, though, the “Large Universe Cosmology”, where the universe is so large that observers with similar subjective experience will arise multiple times in widely separated regions in spacetime. One could then use the idea of self-locating uncertainty above in order to describe their subjective experiences. I think this is worthless speculation.

    In any case, I don’t see what QBism buys you here. Describing the point of view of a particular copy of an observer sitting in a particular branch of the wavefunction is the bread-and-butter of Many-Worlds. Now if you had a complete description of all the parts of the wavefunction where a similar observer arises I presume you could do something sensible with self-locating uncertainty; but here you are considering the case where you don’t. Well then QBism and Many-Worlds will give you pretty much the same description of the point of view that you do have information about. With the difference that QBism can hysterically denies the possibility of these other observers even existing.

  40. Devin Bayer says:

    By SLU I do mean the uncertainty that comes after splitting. That same kind of uncertainty also applies more generally in any multiverse scenario, including just an infinitely large space-time as you mention. Because you cannot definitively pick yourself out from all the different possible versions of you, you are effectively all of them.

    This is related to the principle of Indistinguishability of identical particles. Since this is a necessary principles of QM, if you don’t consider it you may not be able to derive an accurate subjective experience. So if SLU is a real feature of our experience, i.e. we are basically large indistinguishable particles, then you can’t describe someone’s subjective experience accurately by just considering one branch.

    The only reason to invoke SLU for this discussion is to suggest the objective wavefunction is unknowable. Then the perspective of the observers becomes the only thing describable; that seems close to the main subjective claims of QBism.

    Of course there are still many worlds and other observers in superpositions – it doesn’t do anything to save the objective claims of QBism. But the subjective part and the objective part don’t really depend on each other.

  41. Mateus Araújo says:

    We are not “basically large indistinguishable particles”. We are very complex arrangements of indistinguishable particles. The idea that such an arrangement is repeated anywhere is in the universe is controversial, to say the least.

    I’m also a bit confused by your terminology. What is “the objective wavefunction”? The complete wavefunction of the universe? Well yes it’s completely hopeless to know that, I don’t think anybody disagrees.

    And what is the subjective wavefunction? Is it just the part of the universal wavefunction described from a particular observer’s point of view? That would still be objectively real, calling it subjective is a bit misleading, as “subjective” means something completely different in QBism.

  42. Devin Bayer says:

    By subjective I mean relative to an observer and doesn’t tell you directly about an objective reality; it describes the observer: this mind, what he knows, his beliefs, his relationship to reality. I think this is a valid interpretation of what QBist’s are saying the wavefunction is.

    By objective I mean it can be described without reference to an observer, not necessarily the complete universal wavefunction. However, if we are repeated infinite times in the multiverse and SLU is a general feature, then the only objective wavefunction which accurately describes the experiences of an observer is the universal wavefunction. Because if you consider just one branch you’re missing the other branches that contribute to the observer’s experience.

    So all that’s left is the subjective. I consider this a possibility; I can see you aren’t convinced of that :) Well, it’s my best attempt to make sense of QBism.

  43. Mateus Araújo says:

    I don’t think this is a satisfactory definition of subjective. As a trivial example, in Newtonian mechanics the velocity of a particle from some observer’s point of view will be relative to that observer. Nevertheless, it’s a perfectly objective quantity. I think a clearer definition is that a subjective thing is a property of somebody’s mind, and an objective thing is a property of the world (I mean, the world outside that person’s mind, as the contents of a brain are still perfectly objective).

    With this definition even the wavefunction ascribed by an observer repeated over and over again in a large multiverse will be objective. Not that I think such observers exist.

  44. Louis McCartan says:

    Jacques I find it strange how your link to a summary of enactivism comes from Amanda Gefter. Someone who is openly and fundamentally a solipsist….

    She even specifies in that article that we all live in different universes. Separate from one another.
    If that isn’t solipsism I don’t know what is.

    Funny how compatible QBism is with solipsistic points of view…

Comments are closed.